Moral opposition to change—to the erosion of cultural monotony—induced by the processes of globalization has deep roots. Plato’s, and his student Aristotle’s, praise of self-sufficiency (autarkia) is at the root of their general hostility to trade, their insistence on the distinction between Greeks and non-Greeks (i.e., “barbarians,” so-called because instead of speaking Greek, their words seemed to sound like “bar bar bar”), and their suspicion of chrematistic, or money-making. Thus, in Book IV of Plato’s dialogue The Republic, it is agreed that a polis (or city-state) should be of a size and so structured as to be “sufficient and one.” Aristotle argued in Book VII, Chapter 4 of The Politics that a state (the translator’s term for polis), “when composed of too few, is not, as a state ought to be, self-sufficient; when of too many, though self-sufficient in all mere necessaries, as a nation [ethnos in Greek] may be, it is not a state, being almost incapable of constitutional government. For who can be the general of such a vast multitude, or who the herald, unless he have the voice of a Stentor?” Interdependence beyond the small embrace of the polis was considered perilous to unity and to autarkia; the extraordinary experience of Greek commerce in the ancient world was upending established moral orders and entrenched ruling classes by introducing new ideas, among them democracy and liberty, even to the point of questioning and undermining slavery, as Karl Popper documents in The Open Society and its Enemies. Plato and his students sought to preserve static social relations—analogous to his theory of unchanging forms—that were being overturned by globalization.
Ever since Plato’s assault on the open society, critics of globalization have tended to view cultural innovation and exchange as a pure loss rather than as the emergence of new forms of human life that increase the available store of possible human understandings and experiences.
The modern form of that yearning for “unity” and the attendant criticism of globalization focuses on “identity.” According to journalist Nadav Eyal in Revolt: The Worldwide Uprising against Globalization, “Economic globalization poses a significant threat to identity. It inevitably injects universal values into the local discourse, because of its need for supranational relations. Prosperity cannot be achieved alone, and the need for the economy to interact globally does not coexist easily with exclusive national power structures and community.” Setting aside the reification of globalization as an “it” that “needs” things, Eyal overlooks the fact that globalization is and always has been constitutive of identity. There are no “pure identities,” just as there are no “pure races” or “pure cultures.” Identities are constituted by the interplay of many influences, the intersections of ideas, trends, customs, practices, and experiences. As Jeremy Waldron asks, “What if there has been nothing but mélange all the way down? What if cultures have always been implicated with one another, through trade, war, curiosity, and other forms of inter-communal relation? What if the mingling of cultures is as immemorial as cultural roots themselves? What if purity and homogeneity have always been myths?”
The anti-liberal writer Patrick Deneen enthusiastically embraces the illiberal ideas of Plato, whom he curiously refers to as “the Greeks,” as if Plato represented them all, including those Plato lambastes in his writings. Deneen blames globalization for the creation of identities that are “globally homogeneous, the precondition for a fungible global elite who readily identify other members capable of living in a cultureless and placeless world defined above all by liberal norms of globalized indifference toward shared fates of actual neighbors and communities. This in turn induces the globalized irresponsibility that was reflected in the economic interactions that precipitated the 2008 economic crisis but which is assuaged by calls for ‘social justice,’ generally to be handled through the depersonalized levers of the state.”
Besides the sweeping economic claims (which notably ignore irresponsible domestic governmental policies in the United States that were ostensibly intended to secure ownership of homes for all Americans regardless of financial capability but instead created a massive real estate bubble, financial contagion, and global crisis), Deneen misunderstands what economic interdependence entails. Trade tends to make people more connected to others and more interested in their welfare, precisely because their prosperity is entwined more when they trade than when they don’t. Indeed, the prosperity of one community is beneficial to that of those with whom they trade, contrary to the zero-sum, beggar-thy-neighbor view embraced by anti-globalization advocates. Deneen identifies as the beneficiaries of globalization not the low-income people who have seen their real incomes rise as prices of goods, telecommunication, travel, and previously unimaginable things have plummeted but instead a shadowy “fungible global elite,” which is an old trope in the repertoire of illiberalism, that of the “rootless cosmopolitans.” As the economist Jean-Baptiste Say noted,