The scholar, financier, and statesman David Ricardo (1772–1823) is credited with first clearly identifying comparative advantage. He did so in Chapter 7 (“On Foreign Trade”) of his 1817 treatise, On the Principles of Political Economy and Taxation. Ricardo used a simple example to show that under reasonable assumptions, even if the Portuguese were technically superior to the English at producing both wine and cloth, if the Portuguese’s superiority over the English at producing wine was greater than their superiority over the English at producing cloth, both the English and the Portuguese would gain if the English specialized at producing cloth, the Portuguese specialized at producing wine, and then each country freely traded with the other.
Ever since Ricardo offered his explanation of what still appears to many people to be a surprising conclusion, the case for free trade has regularly been said to rest on comparative advantage. While correct, the common interpretation of this fact misses an important reality. This common interpretation holds that a pattern of comparative advantage exists and then gives rise to the pattern of specialization and trade that reflects the pre-existing comparative advantages. This sequence often happens in the real world but not always.
Adam Smith (1723–1790), whose 1776 Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations was published 41 years before Ricardo’s treatise, demonstrated that specialization is advantageous even without a pre-existing pattern of comparative advantage. For Smith, specialization improves workers’ or businesses’ technical proficiency at producing the goods and services in which they specialize. By concentrating on doing a particular task, each producer over time becomes better at performing that task. That is, by specializing, each producer creates for itself a comparative advantage. For Smith, specialization is the source of comparative advantage (although Smith was unaware of this principle’s full reality); for Ricardo, specialization is the result of comparative advantage.
Both Smith and Ricardo are correct. Taken together, their analyses identify a virtuous cycle of improvement in economic productivity. Specialization begets greater comparative advantages, while greater comparative advantages increase the benefits of specialization. This is one surprise; combining Smith’s analysis with Ricardo’s reveals others.
By concentrating his or her productive efforts on a particular task, a specialized producer further improves his or her skills at doing the task for which that person has a comparative advantage, thereby becoming an economically worse performer of other tasks.
Consider the deck-building example. Despite your being technically better at carpentry than Jones, it pays to employ Jones to build your deck. Suppose, as Adam Smith predicts, your concentrating your time working as a radiologist improves your radiology skills and causes your annual salary to rise to $252,000. At your higher salary, building the deck yourself would cost you $21,000 rather than $20,000. Your becoming a better radiologist makes you, economically, a worse—that is, a more costly—deck builder even though your proficiency at carpentry hasn’t declined.
More surprisingly, your becoming a better radiologist makes Jones, compared to you, an economically better deck builder—even if Jones’s technical proficiency at carpentry remains unchanged. His cost of building the deck ($14,000) was 70 percent of your cost of doing so ($20,000) at your previous wages. Now that your radiology skills have improved and your wages are higher, however, Jones’s cost of building the deck is only 66.7 percent of your new cost of doing so ($21,000). Your improved radiology skills economically improves Jones’s carpentry skills in comparison to yours. Put differently, the improvement in your comparative advantage at radiology improved Jones’s comparative advantage at building decks.
You’re obviously made better off by becoming a better radiologist. But is Jones made better off by the resulting improvement of his comparative advantage at building decks? Possibly, but not necessarily. If the amount that you pay Jones to build your deck isn’t increased by your improved skills at radiology, Jones reaps no benefit from your improved radiology skills (unless he finds himself in need of the services of a radiologist, but that’s a different story). But two facts here are worth noting. First, Jones isn’t harmed by your becoming a better radiologist. Second, Jones is potentially made better off by your becoming a better radiologist.
Before the improvement in your radiology skills, you would have been willing to pay Jones up to $20,000 to build the deck, but not a cent more. Had Jones earlier demanded to be paid, say, $20,500, you would have refused, and he would have had no hope of changing your mind. The reason, of course, is that earlier you could have built the deck yourself for $20,000. But since your radiology skills have improved, you’re now willing to pay him as much as $21,000 to build the deck.
Obviously, you want to pay Jones as little as possible. Whether or not your improved comparative advantage at radiology—meaning also Jones’s improved comparative advantage at building decks—redounds to Jones’s benefit depends on how many people are competing for Jones’s services as a producer. The more intense this competition, the more likely it is that market forces will drive you to share with Jones some of the benefits you reap from your improved radiology skills.
The question of whether and by how much you would be driven by market forces to share with Jones the benefits of your enhanced comparative advantage at radiology can be answered only by investigating the structure and competitiveness of markets—chiefly, the number of buyers and suppliers of deck-building services. Such an investigation is beyond this essay’s scope. It’s enough here to demonstrate the surprising and important fact that when the comparative advantage of party A improves, the comparative advantage of party A’s trading partner—party B—also improves, thus at least potentially increasing party B’s welfare in addition to the certain improvement of party A’s welfare.