Carlos de la Torre’s Populisms: A Quick Immersion reviews the theories and practices of populism over the last century, with a particular focus on Latin American’s versions and the lessons for the current American and European varieties.

Populism accentuates one trend of democracy emphasized by 18th-century philosopher Jean-Jacques Rousseau: the sacralization of “the will of the people.” Populists have conceived of “ ‘the people’ as an organic and homogenous whole that shared one interest and identity,” writes de la Torre. In this perspective, the people, as a group, have a will just like an individual.

Populism adds a second element to democracy: the idealization and glorification of the elected leader. “Populists,” writes de la Torre, “construct the people with one will and interest that is only that of the leader.” “Such leaders claim that they represent and even embody the interests, will and aspirations of a homogeneous people.” As Michael Sata, a Zambian populist leader and one-time president, declared, “Zambia needs a redeemer; Zambians want Moses to redeem them, and I am the redeemer of Zambia!” On the 10th anniversary of his election as president of Venezuela, populist Hugo Chavez said, “Ten years ago, Bolivar — embodied in the will of the people — came back to life,” referring to the 19th-century liberator of the country. As we will see, contemporary European and American populism shares the fundamentals of this approach.

Who is “the people” supposed to be? De la Torre quotes political scientist Nadia Urbinati who notes that “populism entails a pars pro toto [part in lieu of the whole] logic that constructs a part of the population as the authentic people who stand for the sovereign whole.” It follows that populism polarizes society into two enemy camps, fueling confrontation and hatred. Those who challenge the populist leader will thus be branded “enemies of the people” or “enemies of the nation.”

De la Torre shows that both components — the will of the people and its incarnation in a great leader — were present in the populism of the left that emerged in the 1940s and the populism of the right that emerged in the 1980s, although he also suggests that left-wing populism is not quite as bad as right-wing populism. The two sorts of populisms do not “construct the people” in the same way, he writes, borrowing from postmodernist jargon. This means, in reality, that left-wing populists are inclusive of the right people and exclusive of the wrong ones — the latter including consumers as well as individuals with libertarian or classical-liberal values.

In Latin America, right-wing populists are more difficult to find than leftist ones. Among the former, de la Torre mentions Alberto Fujimori in Peru and Juan Perón, president of Argentina from 1946 to 1955 and again from 1973 until his death in 1974. However, the book overlooks an important point: populists always want to increase the power of the state and reduce economic freedom. Populism is a matter of collective rights, not individual liberties. Populists such as Marine Le Pen in France, Mateo Salvini in Italy, and Donald Trump in the United States can be called right-wingers only in the sense that they want to impose (generally) right-wing values, instead of left-wing values, on everybody. De la Torre is more correct when he notes that “populists blur traditional left–right distinctions.”

He could have added that both Trump and U.S. Sen. Elizabeth Warren (D–MA), among other populists, explicitly invoke the will of the people. At the 74th session of the United Nations General Assembly on September 25, 2019, Trump said, “A permanent political class is openly disdainful, dismissive, and defiant of the will of the people.” Warren wants Congress to “reflect the will of the people.”

From Perón to Trump: Many democrats and leftist populists see populism as a mere attempt to improve democracy and populism of the left as different from the rightist version. It is striking how what de la Torre calls “the populist playbook” has been roughly the same in Latin America, Hungary, Turkey, and Trump’s United States. The playbook consists in “reducing the independence of [countervailing] powers and concentrating power in the presidency, wars against the media, control of civil society, colonization of state institutions by loyal followers and discriminatory legalism to punish critics.”

“As with other populists,” de la Torre notes, “[Perón] concentrated power in the hands of the presidency, attacked the media, aimed to control civil society.” At least in regard to the first two areas, Trump has done the same, notably by branding media he does not like as “the enemy of the people.” Bolivian populist president Evo Morales identified the media as his “number one enemy.” In Zambia, Sata used defamation lawsuits against independent media. Trump used the law to attack social media.

However, de la Torre is very misleading when he writes:

Fox News became the official voice and broadcaster of Trump’s administration. He did not need to create a state channel. Fox … functions like Chávez’s or [Ecuadorian dictator Rafael] Correa’s state television.

There is a big difference between a private media outlet deciding to support some idea or politician, on the one hand, and state media controlled by the government and supported by taxpayers, on the other. Arguably, Fox News has become somewhat less servile since de la Torre wrote those lines in 2018. Chávez and Correa strangled the private media “by manipulating the subsidies for the price of paper”; thanks to the remaining degree of free enterprise in the United States, this method of control has been closed to American populist rulers — so far.

In order not to be constrained by laws, “populist presidents packed the courts and institutions of accountability with loyal followers,” de la Torre writes. Like other dictators, populist rulers cannot succeed without a servile press and obedient judges.

Only when democratic institutions are strong and “a complex civil society” exists are populist regimes unable to destroy liberal democracy. For that reason, writes de la Torre, Morales, Correa, and Chávez destroyed democracy, while it survived under Néstor Kirchner in Argentina and the Syriza party in Greece. For the same reason, European countries seem to have (thus far) “restrained the undemocratic impulses of right-wing populist parties.” However, Narenda Modi in India and Jair Bolsonaro in Brazil may succeed in crushing liberal democracy in their countries. The jury is still out on whether American democracy — or, more exactly, “the American Republic,” to acknowledge the fear of democracy expressed in the Federalist Papers and in the deeds of the Founders — will survive the populism of Trump and of the left-wing populists who will likely follow him.

Contrary to what de la Torre seems to imply, however, institutions have not been very effective at restraining the undemocratic impulses of left-wing populist parties. He apparently does not see how unlimited democracy can undermine the institutions protecting individual liberty.

Populism as unlimited democracy: One great feature of de la Torre’s book is its description of how current populism is not that different from the populism that developed in South America in the 1930s and 1940s as well as in Europe more recently. The author quotes sociologist Talcott Parsons about the similarities between 19th-century American agrarian populism and 20th-century McCarthyism, the latter understood as populism of the right. In passing, one would have wished de la Torre had spent more time discussing American populism in the late 19th century.

Latin American populism viewed democracy as largely realized in “the quasi-liturgical incorporation of common people through mass rallies.” In Zambia, Sata “transformed government officials and the rank and file of his own party into sycophants who tried to show greater loyalty than their colleagues.” In his administration, President Trump surrounded himself with courtiers such as chief of staff Mark Meadows, secretary of state Mike Pompeo, commerce secretary Wilbur Ross, economic adviser Peter Navarro, and health care policy adviser Scott Atlas. Before Trump, Abdalá Bucaram in Ecuador “transformed political rallies into spectacles of transgression.” For example, Bucaram “said that one of his rivals had watery sperm, and of another that he had no balls.”

The major drawback of Populisms: A Quick Immersion lies in its analytical framework, derived from a leftist-idealist conception of politics. De la Torre sees democracy as exclusively founded on pluralism, majoritarian power, and the rule of law. He seems to think that the “public sphere” is a panacea for the ensuing conflict between individual liberty and the majority’s power. He believes that more (democratic) politics is the solution to populism instead of its main source. All this constitutes a constant illusion of the left.

While he neglects the strong populist tendencies that have appeared in parts of the United States’ Democratic Party (and that, historically, were already visible when the party had a large constituency of white segregationists), de la Torre presents “Tea Party organizations” as precursors of right-wing populism. He states that “conservatives and libertarians coexisted in these organizations,” which is not false, although we now see that the coexistence was an equivocal one and that libertarian fellow travelers bet on a bad horse.

The author blames Fox News for presenting the United States as a country where “illegal immigrants, criminals, and badly behaving people of color are overrunning America.” This unsourced quote, which the reader will likely attribute to Fox News, is in fact an interpretation by Harvard University’s Theda Skocpol and her former student Vanessa Williamson in a book critical of both the Tea Party and Fox News. To be fair to de la Torre, his book eschews footnotes altogether, no doubt to make it more accessible, but this is not without danger.

It is true that Trump “has disfigured and eroded democracy,” but left-wing populism is also a clear and present danger. De la Torre is often carried away by his distaste for Trump. In contrast, he considers Sen. Bernie Sanders (D–VT) as a “light populist” and does not mention other would-be populist rulers on the American left such as Warren and Rep. Alexandria Ocasio-Cortez (D–NY). The next U.S. populist president may be “on the left,” which will simply mean that a different set of individuals will be deemed “the people.”

In reality, democracy is always on the verge of elected tyranny and what de la Torre identifies as “competitive authoritarianism,” which points to the danger represented by populism. To his credit, he ends his book by warning “democrats and progressives” and “the left” to “be wary of being seduced by populism.” He should reflect on the conditions under which democracy can be reconciled with individual liberty.

Unrealistic promises: Does he have the right analytical framework and vocabulary? De la Torre argues that the “neoliberal model” explains popular resistance as if political regimes had been characterized by anything resembling laissez-faire capitalism. It is ludicrous to claim that the Trump administration has been “committed to the unregulated market.” (See “The Trump Economy,” Spring 2020.) He credits left-wing populism for criticizing “the reduction of citizens to consumers,” oblivious to the fact that many individuals, especially among the poor, would rather have the influence of consumers on their suppliers than the illusionary power of a citizen on Leviathan.

It is arguably this sort of approach that, over the past decades, has led to the unrealistic promises of democratic demagogues against whom populist demagogues bid up the stakes by making ever more impossible promises to the populace. Populism is a monster begotten by democracy or, at any rate, by the sort of impossible democracy de la Torre is after. Jean-Marie Le Pen (Marine’s father), the long term-president of France’s National Front party (now rechristened National Rally and led by Marine) declared, “I, and only I, incarnate democracy.”

De la Torre does mention a crucial danger even in the so-called communal form of populist ideal as defended by Bolivian intellectuals: “individual rights are subordinated to collective rights.” He quotes one of those intellectuals, Felix Patzi, who wrote that in “the indigenous communities, democratic rules do not apply, but a form of authoritarianism based on consensus.” It is not clear what this consensual authoritarianism can be, except that some people are bullied to “consent” to some majority or minority.

Missing economic analysis: Many of de la Torre’s contradictions may be attributable to the fact that his economic analysis is skimpy if not nonexistent. He reviews sociological and political theories of populism but does not consider economic theories that show the impossibility of the populist “will of the people.” He would have benefited from considering social choice theory as initiated by Kenneth Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem and presented to political scientists in William Riker’s 1982 classic Liberalism Against Populism. It is precisely because “the people” are not homogeneous that the “will of the people” is nonsensical, that populism is a chimera, and that a strong leader is deemed necessary to substitute for “the (imaginary) people.”

Precisely for this reason, populism cannot avoid defining “the people” as only a faction of people (plural) and exciting this faction against foreign and domestic enemies. No surprise, then, that once in power, populists “attempt to transform a diverse population into the image of the people that is held by the leader.” One does not make this social omelet without breaking individual eggs.

Although de la Torre does not seem to be aware of public choice theory (another branch of economics), he inadvertently provides hints of its relevance to understanding populism. The relation between the populist ruler and his followers is partly based on clientelism: the former buys the support of the latter with special favors. Think about farmers and large manufacturers under Trump, although he only partly compensated for the loss his trade wars inflicted on most of them.

Conclusion: Here is a well-kept secret: We are not obliged to choose between two sorts of totalitarian democracy — between, on one hand, the populist version where an elected ruler imposes a nonexistent “will of the people” on some of the people and, on the other hand, the philosopher-king version where a minority of intellectuals and experts impose their values, lifestyles, and diktats on the majority or a minority of individuals. We are not obliged to choose between a left-wing and right-wing populism or, if we prefer this terminology, to choose between socialism and fascism.

The well-kept secret is that another alternative exists, one that covers a large spectrum of classical liberal or libertarian systems designed to prevent tyranny rather than to create nirvana on earth, to give liberty back to the people viewed as individuals instead of power to an imagined homogeneous people.

Populisms: A Quick Immersion would have been more enlightening if it had revealed that secret.