Vast numbers of Americans today look to Washington for a rich array of “entitlements” that speak of nothing so much as the illusion of something for nothing. And politicians nurture that illusion, propelling us all in the downward spiral that Thomas Hobbes aptly called a war of all against all. Stated otherwise, as contributors to public largesse become fewer and recipients more numerous, the downward spiral becomes a death spiral. And we are headed in that direction as discipline continues to erode.
Finally, and closely related, let me little more than mention the economic implications of effectively unlimited government as I expect that others on the panel will address those more fully. By this point in human history, and especially after the collapse of the socialist experiments of the 20th century, we have a fairly clear understanding of the connection between liberty and prosperity—a connection that Adam Smith articulated so well in 1776, 44 and economists like Mises, Hayek, and Friedman, among many others, have refined and extended in our own time. What that understanding points to, once again, is the prescience of the Framers in drafting a constitution dedicated to securing our liberty and hence our extraordinary prosperity. But neither liberty nor prosperity is guaranteed by a mere parchment, especially by one that is ignored. The American economy has proven resilient enough to withstand the blows imposed by the galloping government of the 20th century—although we will never know how much more prosperous we might have been had that government been better reined. In future, however, to the extent we ignore the lessons of economics we invite the consequences that have befallen so many other nations that have chosen economic planning over economic liberty. And the basic lesson of economics is that liberty, property, and contract are the fundamental preconditions of prosperity.
What Is to Be Done?
We did not create our overextended, unconstitutional government overnight. We cannot restore constitutional government overnight—too many people have come to rely on the irresponsible promises that have been made. But we can begin the process of restoration. For that, the most important thing to do now is to start restoring a constitutional ethos in the nation. And that should be the business of all branches, not simply the Court, which can hardly do the job by itself, even if it were the right body to do so. What we have here, in short, is not simply or even mainly a legal problem. Rather, it is a political and, more deeply still, a moral problem.
Because I have discussed what needs to be done in some detail in chapter 3 of the Cato Handbook on Policy, 45 copies of which are available in every congressional office, I will simply outline those proposals here.
Limits on government today, when we’ve had them, have come largely from political and budgetary rather than from constitutional considerations. It has not been because of any perceived lack of constitutional authority that government in recent years has failed to undertake a program but because of practical limits on the power of government to tax and borrow—and even those limits have failed in times of economic prosperity. To restore truly limited government, therefore, we have to do more than define the issues as political or budgetary. We have to go to the heart of the matter and raise the underlying constitutional questions. In a word, we have to ask the most fundamental question of all: Does the government have the authority, the constitutional authority, to do what it is doing?
That means, of course, that we are going to have to come to grips with the present state of public debate on the subject. It surely counts for something that a substantial number of Americans—to say nothing of the organs of public opinion—have little apprehension of or appreciation for the Constitution’s limits on activist government. Thus, when thinking about how and how fast to reduce government, we have to recognize that the Court, after nearly 70 years of arguing otherwise, is hardly in a position, by itself, to relimit government in the far-reaching way a properly applied Constitution requires. But neither does Congress at this point have sufficient moral authority, even if it wanted to, to end tomorrow the vast array of programs it has enacted over the years with insufficient constitutional authority.
For either Congress or the Court to be able to do fully what should be done, therefore, a proper foundation must first be laid. In essence, the climate of opinion must be such that a sufficiently large portion of the American public stands behind the changes that are undertaken. When enough people come forward to ask—indeed, to demand—that government limit itself to the powers it is given in the Constitution, thereby freeing individuals, families, and communities to solve their own problems, we will know we are on the right track.
Fortunately, a change in the climate of opinion on such basic questions has been under way for some time now. The debate today is very different than it was in the 1960s and 1970s. But there is a good deal more to be done before Congress and the courts are able to move in the right direction in any far-reaching way.
To continue the process, Congress should take the lead by engaging in constitutional debate in Congress, much as happened in the 19th century, thereby encouraging constitutional debate in the nation. That was urged by the House Constitutional Caucus during the 104th Congress. Under the leadership of House freshmen like J. D. Hayworth and John Shadegg of Arizona, Sam Brownback of Kansas, and Bob Barr of Georgia, together with a few more senior congressmen like Richard Pombo of California, an informal Constitutional Caucus was established in the “radical” 104th Congress. Unfortunately, the caucus has been moribund since then. It needs to be revived—along with the spirit of the 104th Congress—and its work needs to be expanded.
By itself, of course, neither the caucus nor the entire Congress can solve the problem before us. To be sure, in a reversal of all human experience, Congress in a day could agree to limit itself to its enumerated powers and then roll back the countless programs it has enacted by exceeding that authority. But it would take authoritative opinions from the Supreme Court, reversing a substantial body of largely post-New Deal decisions, to embed those restraints in “constitutional law”—even if they have been embedded in the Constitution from the outset, the Court’s modern readings of the document notwithstanding.
The ultimate goal of the caucus and Congress, then, should be to encourage the Court to reach such decisions. But history teaches, as noted above, that the Court does not operate entirely in a vacuum—that to some degree public opinion is the precursor and seedbed of its decisions. Thus, the more immediate goal of the caucus should be to influence the debate in the nation by influencing the debate in Congress. To do that, it is not necessary or even desirable, in the present climate, that every member of Congress be a member of the caucus—however worthy that end might ultimately be—but it is necessary that those who join the caucus be committed to its basic ends. And it is necessary that members establish a clear agenda for reaching those ends.
To reduce the problem to its essence, every day members of Congress are besieged by requests to enact countless measures to solve endless problems. Indeed, one imagines that no problem is too personal or too trivial not to warrant federal attention, no less. Yet most of the “problems” Congress spends most of its time addressing—from health care to day care to retirement security to economic competition—are simply the personal and economic problems of life that individuals, families, and firms, not governments, should be addressing—quite apart from the absence of constitutional authority to address them.
Properly understood and used, then, the Constitution can be a valuable ally in the efforts of the caucus and Congress to reduce the size and scope of government. For in the minds and hearts of most Americans, it remains a revered document, however little it may be understood by a substantial number of them.
If the Constitution is to be thus used, however, the principal misunderstanding that surrounds it must be recognized and addressed. In particular, the modern idea that the Constitution, without further amendment, is an infinitely elastic document that allows government to grow to meet public demands of whatever kind must be challenged. More Americans than presently do must come to appreciate that the Framers, who were keenly aware of the expansive tendencies of government, wrote the Constitution precisely to check that kind of thinking and that possibility. To be sure, they meant for government to be our servant, not our master, but they meant it to serve us in a very limited way—by securing our rights, as the Declaration of Independence says, and by doing those few other things that government does best, as spelled out in the Constitution.
In all else, as discussed above, we were meant to be free—to plan and live our own lives, to solve our own problems, which is what freedom is all about. Some may characterize that vision as tantamount to saying, “You’re on your own,” but that kind of response simply misses the point. In America individuals, families, and organizations have never been “on their own” in the most important sense. They have always been members of communities, of civil society, where they could live their lives and solve their problems by following a few simple rules about individual initiative and responsibility, respect for property and promise, and charity toward the few who need help from others. Massive government planning and programs have upset that natural order of things—less so in America than elsewhere, but very deeply all the same.
Those are the issues that need to be discussed, both in human and in constitutional terms. We need, as a people, to rethink our relationship to government. We need to ask not what government can do for us but what we can do for ourselves and, where necessary, for others—not through government but apart from government, as private citizens and organizations. That is what the Constitution was written to enable. It empowers government in a very limited way. It empowers people—by leaving them free—in every other way.
To proclaim and eventually secure that vision of a free people, the Constitutional Caucus should reconstitute itself and rededicate itself to that end in the 109th Congress and at the beginning of every Congress hereafter. Standing apart from Congress, the caucus should nonetheless be both of and above Congress—as the constitutional conscience of Congress. Every member of Congress, before taking office, swears to support the Constitution—hardly a constraining oath, given the modern Court’s open-ended reading of the document. Members of the caucus should dedicate themselves to the deeper meaning of that oath. They should support the Constitution the Framers gave us, as amended by subsequent generations, not as “amended” by the Court’s expansive interpretations.
Acting together, the members of the caucus could have a major impact on the course of public debate in this nation—not least, by virtue of their numbers. What is more, there is political safety in those numbers. As Benjamin Franklin might have said, no single member of Congress is likely to be able to undertake the task of restoring constitutional government on his own, for in the present climate he would surely be hanged, politically, for doing so. But if the caucus hangs together, the task will be made more bearable and enjoyable—and a propitious outcome made more likely.
On the agenda of the caucus, then, should be those specific undertakings that will best stir debate and thereby move the climate of opinion. Drawn together by shared understandings, and unrestrained by the need for serious compromise, the members of the caucus are free to chart a principled course and employ principled means, which they should do.
They might begin, for example, by surveying opportunities for constitutional debate in Congress, then making plans to seize those opportunities. Clearly, when new bills are introduced, or old ones are up for reauthorization, an opportunity is presented to debate constitutional questions. But even before that, when plans are discussed in party sessions, members should raise constitutional issues. Again, the caucus might study the costs and benefits of eliminating clearly unconstitutional programs, the better to determine which can be eliminated most easily and quickly.
Above all, the caucus should look for strategic opportunities to employ constitutional arguments. Too often, members of Congress fail to appreciate that if they take a principled stand against a seemingly popular program—and state their case well—they can seize the moral high ground and prevail ultimately over those who are seen in the end to be more politically craven.
All of that will stir constitutional debate—which is just the point. For too long in Congress that debate has been dead, replaced by the often dreary budget debate. This nation was not established by men with green eyeshades. It was established by men who understood the basic character of government and the basic right to be free. That debate needs to be revived. It needs to be heard not simply in the courts—where it is twisted through modern “constitutional law”—but in Congress as well.
Before concluding, Mr. Chairman, let me leave the subcommittee with three basic recommendations, which I have discussed more fully in the Cato Handbook I referenced above:
- Enact nothing without first consulting the Constitution for proper authority and then debating that question on the floors of the House and the Senate.
- Move toward restoring constitutional government by carefully returning power wrongly taken over the years from the states and the people.
- Reject the nomination of judicial candidates who do not appreciate that the Constitution is a document of delegated, enumerated, and thus limited powers.
Conclusion
America is a democracy in the most fundamental sense of that idea: authority, or legitimate power, rests ultimately with the people. But the people have no more right to tyrannize each other through democratic government than government itself has to tyrannize the people. When they constituted us as a nation by ratifying the Constitution and the amendments that have followed, our forefathers gave up only certain of their powers, enumerating them in a written constitution. We have allowed those powers to expand beyond all moral and legal bounds—at the price of our liberty and our well-being. The time has come to return those powers to their proper bounds, to reclaim our liberty, and to enjoy the fruits that follow.
BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH OF ROGER PILON
Roger Pilon is vice president for legal affairs at the Cato Institute where he holds the B. Kenneth Simon Chair in Constitutional Studies and directs Cato’s Center for Constitutional Studies, which he founded in 1989. Prior to joining Cato he held five senior posts in the Reagan Administration, at the Office of Personnel Management, the State Department, and the Justice Department. A philosopher of law by profession, Mr. Pilon did his undergraduate work at Columbia University, earning a B.A. in philosophy in 1971. He did his graduate work at the University of Chicago, earning an M.A. in 1972 and a Ph.D. in 1979, both in philosophy. In 1988 he earned a J.D. from the George Washington University School of Law. He taught philosophy at the California State University at Sonoma in 1977 and philosophy of law at the Emory University School of Law from 1978 to 1979. From 1979 to 1980 he was a national fellow at the Hoover Institution on War, Revolution and Peace at Stanford University and from 1980 to 1981 an Institute for Educational Affairs fellow at the Institute for Humane Studies in Menlo Park, California. Mr. Pilon has published and lectured widely in the area of moral, political, and legal theory. He testifies often before Congress and is a frequent guest on television and radio programs discussing legal issues of the day. In 1989 the National Press Foundation and the Commission on the Bicentennial of the U.S. Con¬stitution presented him with the Benjamin Franklin Award for excellence in writing on the U.S. Constitution. In 2001 Columbia University’s School of General Studies awarded him its Alumni Medal of Distinction.
1 A biographical sketch is attached.
2 The Tenth Amendment states: “The powers not delegated to the United States by the Constitution, nor prohibited by it to the States, are reserved to the States respectively, or to the people.”
3 For a discussion of the Progressives’ approach to the Constitution, see Richard A. Epstein, “The Monopolistic Vices of Progressive Constitutionalism,” 2004–2005 Cato Supreme Court Review 11 (2005); Richard A. Epstein, How Progressives Rewrote the Constitution (Cato Institute, 2006) (forthcoming).
4 See Arthur Harrison Cole ed., Industrial and Commercial Correspondence of Alexander Hamilton 247 (A. M. Kelley, 1968).
5 Id.
6 Letter to Henry Lee, in 6 The Writings of James Madison, at 81n. (Gaillard Hunt ed., G. P. Putnam’s Sons, 1906) (original emphasis).
7 Act of Feb. 12, 1794, 6 Stat. 13.
8 4 Annals of Cong. 170 (1794).
9 6 Annals of Cong. 1727 (1796).
10 Id. at 1724.
11 The Congress shall have Power To lay and collect Taxes, Imposts and Excises, to pay the Debts and provide for the common Defense and General Welfare of the United States; …”
12 4 Reg. Deb. 1632–34 (1828). Madison made a similar point on several occasions. See, e.g., James Madison, “Report on Resolutions,” in 6 The Writings of James Madison 357 (Gaillard Hunt ed., G. P. Putnam’s Sons, 1900): “Money cannot be applied to the general welfare, otherwise than by an application of it to some particular measure conducive to the general welfare. Whenever, therefore, money has been raised by the general authority, and is to be applied to a particular measure, a question arises whether the particular measure be within the enumerated authorities vested in Congress. If it be, the money requisite for it may be applied to it; if it be not, no such application can be made.” (emphasis in original). And Jefferson also addressed the issue. See, e.g., “Letter from Thomas Jefferson to Albert Gallatin” (June 16, 1817) in Writings of Thomas Jefferson 91 (Paul Leicester Ford ed., New York, 1899): “[O]ur tenet ever was, and, indeed, it is almost the only landmark which now divides the federalists from the republicans, that Congress had not unlimited powers to provide for the general welfare, but were restrained to those specifically enumerated; and that, as it was never meant they should … raise money for purposes which the enumeration did not place under their action; consequently, that the specification of powers is a limitation of the purpose for which they may raise money.”
13 Charles Warren, Congress as Santa Claus 32 (Arno Press, 1932).
14 H.R. 10203, 49th Cong., 2d Sess. (1887).
15 18 Cong. Rec. 1875 (1887).
16Kansas v. Colorado 206 U.S. 46, 89 (1907).
17 Contrast that with Congress’s enactment of the Gun-Free Schools Act of 1990 (18 U.S.C. § 922 (q)(1)(A) (1988 ed., Supp. V), which the Court found unconstitutional in 1995, holding for the first time in nearly 60 years that Congress had exceeded its authority under the Commerce Clause. United States v. Lopez, 514 U.S. 549 (1995). In enacting the statute, Congress had not even bothered to cite its constitutional authority for doing so.
18The Nation, Aug. 9, 1900, p. 105.
19 See Robert S. Summers, Pragmatic Instrumentalism: America’s Leading Theory of Law, 5 Cornell Law Forum 15 (1978).
20 Progressives did not limit their attention to economic regulation. In 1927, for example, we find Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes, the “Yankee from Olympus,” writing for the Court to uphold a Virginia statute that authorized the sterilization of people thought to be of insufficient intelligence. Buck v. Bell, 274 U.S. 200 (1927). There followed in this country some 70,000 sterilizations. For an insightful discussion of the case and surrounding issues, see William E. Leuchtenburg, Mr. Justice Holmes and Three Generations of Imbeciles, ch. 1 in The Supreme Court Reborn: The Constitutional Revolution in the Age of Roosevelt (1995).
21Buck v. Bell, supra note 20, is a good example, as is Euclid v. Ambler Realty, 272 U.S. 365 (1926), which upheld a zoning ordinance involving a regulatory taking of property without compensation.
22 Thus, on “Black Monday,” May 27, 1935, in three 9–0 decisions, the Court invalidated the National Industrial Recovery Act and the Frazier-Lemke Act on mortgage moratoria and, in Humphrey’s Executor v. United States, circumscribed the president’s power to remove members of independent regulatory commissions. For a discussion of this era, see Leuchtenberg, The Supreme Court Reborn, supra note 20.
23 262 U.S. 1, 65–66 (1936).
24 7 U.S.C.A. 601 (1933).
25 49 Stat. 620 (1935).
26 301 U.S. 619, 640 (1937).
27 Id.
28 Id. at 641.
29 301 U.S. 619 (1937); see also Wickard v. Filburn, 317 U.S. 111 (1942)./p>
30 See Randy E. Barnett, The Original Meaning of the Commerce Clause, 68 U. Chi. L. Rev. 101 (2000); Brief of Amicus Curiae Cato Institute, Jones v. United States, 529 U.S. 848 (2000) (visited Oct. 21, 2005).; Cf., Richard A. Epstein, The Proper Scope of the Commerce Power, 73 Va. Law Review 1387 (1987).
31 304 U.S. 104 (1938). For a devastating critique of the politics behind the Carolene Products case, see Geoffrey P. Miller, The True Story of Carolene Products, 1987 Supreme Cato Review 397.
32 I have discussed that methodology in Roger Pilon, Foreword: Substance and Method at the Court, 2002–2003 Cato Supreme Court Review vii. (2003).
33 See Bernard H. Siegan, Economic Liberties and the Constitution (1980).
34 See Gary Lawson, Making a Federal Case Out of It: Sabri v. United States and the Constitution of Leviathan. 2003–2004 Cato Supreme Court Review 119 (2004).
35 Letter from Franklin D. Roosevelt to Rep. Samuel B. Hill (July 6, 1935), in 4 The Public Papers and Addresses of Franklin D. Roosevelt 91–92 (Samuel I. Rosenman ed., 1938).
36 Rexford G. Tugwell, A Center Report: Rewriting the Constitution, Center Magazine, March 1968, at 20. This is a fairly clear admission that the New Deal was skating not simply on thin ice but on no ice at all. For comments from the other side, see, e.g., Gary Lawson, The Rise and Rise of the Administrative State, 107 Harvard Law Review 1231 (1994): “The post-New Deal administrative state is unconstitutional, and its validation by the legal system amounts to nothing less than a bloodless constitutional revolution;” Richard A. Epstein, Commerce Clause, supra note 30, at 1388: “I think that the expansive construction of the [commerce] clause accepted by the New Deal Supreme Court is wrong, and clearly so.”
37 That was pretty much the view of Justice Holmes in his famous dissent in Lochner v. New York, 198, U.S. 45 (1905). Declaring that the case was “decided upon an economic theory which a large part of the country does not entertain,” and adding that his “agreement or disagreement [with the theory] has nothing to do with the right of a majority to embody their opinions in the law,” Holmes proceeded to read out of the Constitution all economic substance: “a constitution is not intended to embody a particular economic theory, whether of paternalism and the organic relation of the citizen to the state or of laissez faire.” Id. at 75. But we find a similar view in many modern conservatives as well. Thus, Robert H. Bork speaks of the “two opposing principles” of what he calls the “Madisonian dilemma.” Our first principle, Bork says, “is self-government, which means that in wide areas of life majorities are entitled to rule, if they wish, simply because they are majorities. The second is that there are nonetheless some things majorities must not do to minorities, some areas of life in which the individual must be free of majority rule.” Robert H. Bork, The Tempting of America 139 (Touchstone, 1990). That gets Madison exactly backward. Madison’s vision was that in wide areas of life individuals are entitled to be free simply because they are born free. Nonetheless, in some areas majorities are entitled to rule because we have authorized them to rule, giving them powers “few and defined.”
38 John Locke, The Second Treatise of Government, in Two Treatises of Government (1960) (1690).
39 I have discussed this issue more fully in Roger Pilon, Foreword: Can Law this Uncertain Be Called Law? 2003–2004 Cato Supreme Court Review vii (2004).
40 For my critique of an opinion by Justice Anthony Kennedy distinguishing four “levels” of review, Turner Broadcasting System v. FCC, 512 U.S. 622 (1994), see Roger Pilon, A Modest Proposal on “Must-Carry,” the 1992 Cable Act, and Regulation Generally: Go Back to Basics, 17 Hastings Comm/Ent. Law Journal 41 (1994).
41 That is arguably what happened in McConnell v. FEC, 124 S. Ct. 619 (2003), upholding the McCain-Feingold Campaign Finance Act, 116 Stat. 81 (2002), which President George W. Bush signed while saying it was unconstitutional. See Eric S. Jaffee, McConnell v. FEC: Rationing Speech to Prevent “Undue Influence,” 2003–2004 Cato Supreme Court Review 245 (2004).
42 See Robert J. Reinstein, Completing the Constitution: The Declaration of Independence, Bill of Rights, and Fourteenth Amendment, 47 Temple Law Review 361 (1993). In 1833 the Court had ruled that the Bill of Rights applied only against the government created by the document (the U.S. Constitution) to which it was appended. Barron v. Mayor and City Council of Baltimore, 32 U.S. 243 (1833).
43 Warren, Santa Claus, supra note 13, front page, citing only to 22d Cong., 1st Sess.
44 Adam Smith, An Inquiry Into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations (1776).
45 Roger Pilon, Congress, the Courts, and the Constitution, ch. 3, in Cato Handbook on Policy (2005).