1 Merriam-Webster Online: “1. martial sounds and the movement of soldiers across the stage—used as a stage direction in Elizabethan drama; 2. clamor, excitement, and feverish or disordered activity.”
2 Examples include deterrent threats, military alliances, overseas troop deployments for basing or state-building and humanitarian missions, and war. A similar definition is given by Fareed Zakaria. See Zakaria, From Wealth to Power: The Unusual Origins of America’s World Role (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1998), pp. 1–5.
3 For more on the abuse of worst-case scenarios, see Benjamin H. Friedman, “The Terrible Ifs,” Regulation 30, no. 4. (Winter 2007/8): 32–40. U.S. leaders often construct such scenarios using shoddy political science theories that link the fate of remote regions to U.S. security. The domino theory is an example. Jack Snyder’s works attack several such theories. See Snyder, Myths of Empire: Domestic Politics and International Ambition (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1991).
4 E. E. Schattschneider, The Semi-Sovereign People: A Realist’s View of Democracy in America (New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1960), pp. 1–5.
5 Warner Schilling, “The Defense Budget of 1950,” in Strategy, Politics, and Defense: Budgets, ed. Warner Schilling, Paul Y. Hammond, and Glenn H. Snyder (New York and London: Columbia University Press, 1962); George Tsebelis, Veto Players, How Political Institutions Work (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2002).
6 Theodore Lowi, The End of Liberalism (New York: W. W. Norton, 2009), chap. 6; Thomas J. Christensen, Useful Adversaries: Grand Strategy, Domestic Mobilization, and Sino- American Conflict, 1947–58 (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996).
7 The classic work is Robert Jervis’s Perception and Misperception in International Politics (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1976). See also Daniel Kahneman and Jonathan Renshon, “Hawkish Biases,” in American Foreign Policy and the Politics of Fear: Threat Inflation since 9/11, ed. A. Trevor Thrall and Jane K. Cramer (New York, Routledge, 2008), pp. 79–96.
8 The 9/11 Commission Report (Washington: Government Printing Office, 2004), p. 339.
9 On this model, see John W. Kingdon, Agendas, Alternatives, and Public Policies, 2nd ed. (New York: Longman, 1995), pp. 77–79.
10 John Stuart Mill, On Liberty (London: Longman, Roberts, & Green, 1859).
11 Kenneth Waltz, Foreign Policy and Democratic Politics: The American and British Experience (Boston: Little, Brown, 1967), pp. 267–311. Where the state sees problems clearly and responds appropriately, it resembles the rational-actor model in Graham Allison’s Essence of Decision: Explaining the Cuban Missile Crisis (Boston: Little, Brown, 1971).
12 Exceptions to that tendency include Snyder, Myths of Empire; Stephen Van Evera, “Why States Believe Foolish Ideas: Non-Self-Evaluation by State and Societies,” in Perspectives on Structural Realism, ed. Andrew K. Hanami (New York: Palgrave, 2003), pp. 163–98; Chaim Kaufmann, “Threat Inflation and the Failure of the Marketplace of Ideas: The Selling of the Iraq War,” International Security 29, no. 1 (Summer 2004): 5–48.
13 Pluralism is a diverse school of political science that sees politics through the lens of the conflict of political groups. Pluralists differ on how efficient those conflicts are in producing sound public policy, but they tend to agree that it is the best way to conceive of politics, at least in the United States. See, for example, Arthur F. Bentley, The Process of Government: A Study of Societal Pressures (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1908); David B. Truman, The Governmental Process: Political Interests and Public Opinion (New York: Knopf, 1951); Robert Dahl, Polyarchy: Participation and Opposition (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1972); Charles E. Lindblom, “The Science of ‘Muddling Through,’” Public Administration Review 19, no. 2 (Spring 1959): 79–88. See also Joseph A. Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy (New York: Harper & Brothers, 1947); James Q. Wilson, Bureaucracy: What Government Agencies Do and Why They Do It (New York: Basic Books, 1989).
14 Harvey M. Sapolsky, “The Politics of Risk,” Daedalus 119, no. 4 (Fall 1990): 83–96; Schilling, “Defense Budget of 1950”; A. Trevor Thrall, “A Bear in the Woods? Threat Framing and the Marketplace of Values,” Security Studies 16, no. 3 (2007): 452–88.
15 John W. Kingdon, Agendas, Alternatives, and Public Policies, updated 2nd ed. (Upper Saddle River, NJ: Pearson, 2010), pp. 83–89. A similar idea is posterior rationality, where action is “antecedent to goals.” James March, “Bounded Rationality, Ambiguity, and the Engineering of Choice,” Bell Journal of Economics 9, no. 2 (Autumn, 1978): 593.
16 Another analogy is a court of law. The rational-comprehensive view sees policymakers as judges or juries. Pluralism sees policymakers as lawyers representing narrow interests and the public as an extremely inattentive jury. Whatever the metaphor, the equilibrium condition is conflict. Disagreement with rivals helps the sides define and organize themselves. See Thrall, “A Bear in the Woods?”
17 Madison’s analysis is often read as a guide to protecting minority from majority. But he says that he is concerned with the mischief of factions whether they constitute a majority or minority. See Federalist 10, James Madison, “The Same Subject Continued: The Union as a Safeguard against Domestic Faction and Insurrection,” New York Packet, 1787, http://thomas.loc.gov/home/histdox/fed_10.html.
18 See David Truman, The Governmental Process; also see Edward Banfield, Political Influence (Chicago: Transaction Publishers, 1961).
19 Mancur Olson, The Logic of Collective Action: Public Goods and the Theory of Groups (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971).
20 Even classic public goods such as defense serve private interests, for instance, contractors and military employees. In Olsonian terms, the public organization providing the good, and the contractors it hires become private interests overcoming the collective action problem and ensuring its provision. See Dwight R. Lee, “Public Goods, Politics, and Two Cheers for the Military Industrial Complex,” in Arms, Politics, and the Economy: Historical and Contemporary Perspectives, ed. Robert Higgs (New York: Holmes and Meier, 1990), pp. 22–36.
21 Robert Dahl, A Preface to Democratic Theory (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1956), pp. 124–51.
22 See, for example, Joseph Stiglitz, “Information and the Change in the Paradigm in Economics,” American Economic Review 92, no. 3 (June 2002): 460–501; also see George Akerlof, “The Market for ‘Lemons’: Quality Uncertainty and the Market Mechanism,” Quarterly Journal of Economics 84, no. 3 (August 1970): 488–500.
23 Philip E. Converse, “The Nature and Origin of Belief Systems in Mass Publics,” in Ideology and Discontent, ed. David E. Apter (New York: Free Press, 1964), pp. 206–61. See also John R. Zaller, The Nature and Origins of Mass Opinion (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1992).
24 Sapolsky, “Politics of Risk.”
25 North gives a slightly different definition. Douglass C. North, Institutions, Institutional Change and Economic Performance (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2007), p. 23.
26 Ibid., p. 3.
27 Robert S. Erikson and Laura Stoker, “Caught in the Draft: The Effects of Vietnam Draft Lottery Status on Political Attitudes,” American Political Science Review 105, no. 2 (May 2011): 221–37. On the limited extent to which voters inform themselves about even issues especially important to them, see, for example, Zaller, Nature and Origins of Mass Opinion, p. 18.
28 See, for example, Benjamin Page and Robert Shapiro, The Rational Public: Fifty Years of Trends in Americans’ Policy Preferences (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992), pp. 367–82; also see Jon Western, Selling Intervention and War: The Presidency, the Media, and the American Public (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2005), pp. 15–18.
29 This is a form of path dependence, where a process continues to produce an outcome in the absence of the original causes. Paul Pierson, “Increasing Returns, Path Dependence, and the Study of Politics,” American Political Science Review 94, no. 2 (June 2000): 251–67.
30 Arnold Wolfers. Discord and Collaboration: Essays on International Politics (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1962), pp. 153–54.
31 Ibid., p. 156. See also Randall Schweller, “Neorealism’s Status-Quo Bias: What Security Dilemma?” Security Studies 5, no. 3 (Spring 1996): 90–121.
32 Robert Jervis, “Unipolarity: A Structural Perspective,” World Politics 61, no. 1 (January 2009): 188–213; Richard K. Betts, “The Political Support System for American Primacy,” International Affairs 81, no. 1 (January 2005), pp. 1–14; Harvey M. Sapolsky, Eugene Gholz, and Caitlin Talmadge, U.S. Defense Politics: The Origins of Security Policy (New York: Routledge, 2009), p. 22.
33 Similar arguments are John A. Thompson, “The Exaggeration of American Vulnerability: The Anatomy of a Tradition,” Diplomatic History 16, no. 1 (Winter 1992): 23–44; Christensen, Useful Adversaries; John Schuessler, “Necessity or Choice? Securing Public Consent for War,” paper presented to the Midwest Political Science Association, Chicago, April 15, 2004; Michael Desch, “America’s Liberal Illiberalism: The Ideological Origins of Overreaction in U.S. Foreign Policy,” International Security 32, no. 3 (Winter 2007/8): 7–43; Christopher Layne, Peace of Illusions: American Grand Strategy from 1940 to the Present (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2007).
34 Kenneth N. Waltz, Theory of International Politics (Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley Longman, 1979), pp. 117–23.
35 Colin Elman, “Horses for Courses: Why No Neorealist Theories of Foreign Policy?” Security Studies 6, no. 1 (1996): 7–53.
36 Wolfers compares the behavior of states facing large threats with the predictably similar behavior of people in burning houses. Wolfers, Discord and Collaboration, p. 13. On international pressure’s tendency to overwhelm parochial security policies, see Barry R. Posen, The Sources of Military Doctrine (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1984). On the absence of systemic constraint as a motivation for expansive foreign policy, see Zakaria, From Wealth to Power; Kenneth Waltz, “Structural Realism after the Cold War,” International Security 25, no. 1 (Summer 2000): 5–41; Layne, Peace of Illusions; Jervis, “Unipolarity”; and Nuno Monterio, “Unrest Assured: Why Unipolarity Is Not Peaceful,” International Security 36, no. 3 (Winter 2011/12): 9–40. For realist works exploring domestic pathologies that cause states to harm themselves by ignoring systemic constraints, see, for example, Jack Snyder, Ideology of the Offensive Military Decision-Making and the Disasters of 1914 (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1984); also see Stephen Van Evera, Causes of War: Power and the Roots of Conflict (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2001).
37 North, Institutions, Institutional Change, p. 22.
38 Jervis, “Unipolarity”; Robert W. Tucker and David C. Hendrickson, The Imperial Temptation: The New World Order and America’s Purpose (New York: Council on Foreign Relations, 1992), p. 15.
39 On the idea that position determines behavior, see Thucydides, The History of the Peloponnesian War, trans. Rex Warner (New York, Penguin, 1954), pp. 400–408.
40 Stephen Van Evera, “Primed for Peace: Europe after the Cold War,” International Security 15, no. 1 (Winter 1990/91): 7–57.
41 Mary Ann Heiss, “The Evolution of the Imperial Idea and U.S. National Identity,” Diplomatic History 26, no. 4 (Fall 2002): 511–40; Walter McDougall, Promised Land Crusader State: The American Encounter with the World Since 1776 (New York: Houghton Mifflin, 1997).
42 Layne, Peace of Illusions.
43 That justification is the opposite of the tendency to justify realpolitik with liberal rhetoric. See John Mearsheimer, The Tragedy of Great Power Politics (New York: W. W. Norton, 2001), pp. 21–27.
44 Snyder, Myths of Empire, p. 49.
45 “National security establishment” here refers to government and private organizations with a special interest or select incentive in the provision of defenses. I take the term “national security establishment” from Adam Yarmolinsky, The Military Establishment: Its Impact on American Society (New York: Harper & Row, 1971).
46 Steven P. Rosen, “Testing the Theory of the Military-Industrial Complex,” in Testing the Theory of the Military-Industrial Complex, Steven P. Rosen, ed. (Lexington, MA: Lexington Books, 1973), pp. 23–24. See also, “Militarism” in Stephen Van Evera, “More Causes of War: Misperception and the Roots of Conflict,” Unpublished Manuscript, 2001.
47 Les Aspin, foreword to The Military-Industrial Complex: A Historical Perspective by Paul Koistinen (New York: Praeger, 1980), p. vi.
48 Aaron Wildavsky: “The Two Presidencies,” Trans-Action 4, no. 2 (December 1966): 162–73.
49 Phillip Selznick, Leadership in Administration: A Sociological Interpretation (New York: Harper & Row, 1957), pp. 90–107.
50 Posen, Sources of Military Doctrine, pp. 13–80; Selznick, Leadership in Administration, pp. 10–20.
51 On the way organizational purpose infuses the organization and protects its power structure, see Selznick, Leadership in Administration, pp. 63–64; Posen, Sources of Military Doctrine, p. 36; Wilson, Bureaucracy, pp. 25–26, 246–47.
52 James Q. Wilson, “Innovation in Organization: Notes toward a Theory,” in Approaches to Organizational Design, ed. James O. Thompson (Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, 1971): 195–218; Posen, Sources of Military Doctrine, pp. 29–33, 54–57.
53 An intelligence agency that gets a reputation for politicized assessments may gain temporary support from some politicians, but it will come to be regarded as a propaganda organ and eventually lose support. Sherman Kent, “Estimates and Influence,” Foreign Service Journal 46, no. 4 (April 1969): 11–21.
54 Steve Chan, “The Intelligence of Stupidity: Understanding Failures in Strategic Warning,” American Political Science Review 73, no. 1 (March 1979): 174.
55 Wildavsky, “The Two Presidencies,” p. 167.
56 Schilling, “Defense Budget of 1950.”
57 Sapolsky, Gholz, and Talmadge, U.S. Defense Politics, pp. 68–69, 78.
58 Ibid., pp. 69–74.
59 Peter Trubowitz, Defining the National Interest: Conflict and Change in American Foreign Policy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1998); Ann Markusen et al., The Rise of the Gunbelt: The Military Remapping of Industrial America (New York: Oxford University Press, 1991).
60 Sapolsky, Gholz, and Talmadge, U.S. Defense Politics, chap. 9; Betts, “Political Support System.”
61 Jane K. Cramer, “Militarized Patriotism: Why the U.S. Marketplace of Ideas Failed before the Iraq War,” Security Studies 16, no. 3 (2007): 489–524.
62 Hans J. Morgenthau, “The Purpose of Political Science,” in A Design for Political Science: Scope, Objectives, and Methods, ed. James C. Charlesworth (Philadelphia: American Academy of Political and Social Science, 1966), pp. 63–79.
63 This point shows the limits of the argument made by John Mearsheimer and Stephen Walt, The Israel Lobby and U.S. Foreign Policy (New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2008).
64 Kingdon, Agendas, pp. 58–61. Elite insiders set the range of debate deemed credible by most media. See Brigitte L. Nacos, Yaeli Bloch-Elkon, and Robert Y. Shapiro, Selling Fear: Counterterrorism, the Media, and Public Opinion (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2011), p. 12.
65 Western, Selling Intervention and War, pp. 18–25; Van Evera, “Why States Believe Foolish Ideas.”
66 The media’s professional norms of even-handedness offer a limited check against that species of alarmism. Nacos, Bloch-Elkon, and Shapiro, Selling Fear, pp. 10–11.
67 Kingdon, Agendas. Brief case studies essentially making this point are Steven Livinstone and Todd Eachus, “Humanitarian Crises and U.S. Foreign Policy: Somalia and the CNN Effect Reconsidered,” Political Communication 12, no. 4 (1995): 413–29; Edward Jay Epstein, “Did the Press Uncover Watergate?” Commentary, July 1974, pp. 21–24.
68 On the president’s powers of persuasion, see Richard Neustadt, Presidential Power and the Modern Presidents: The Politics of Leadership (New York: MacMillan, 1960); also see Samuel Kernell, Going Public: New Strategies of Presidential Leadership (Washington: CQ Press, 1986). The extent to which presidents can permanently change opinion amid organized opposition is doubtful, however. See John Mueller, War, Presidents, and Public Opinion (New York: John Wiley, 1973); also see George C. Edwards III, On Deaf Ears: The Limits of the Bully Pulpit (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2003).
69 Neustadt, Politics of Leadership, chap. 3.
70 Lowi, End of Liberalism; Schilling, “Defense Budget of 1950.”
71 Sapolsky, Gholz, and Talmadge, U.S. Defense Politics, pp. 53–55, 127–29.
72 On that tradition, see Jim Cooper and Russell Rumbaugh, “Real Acquisition Reform,” Joint Forces Quarterly 55 (4th Quarter 2009): 59–65.
73 That is a form of what scholars call blowback. Snyder, Myths of Empire, pp. 41–42.
74 Cass Sunstein, Risk and Reason: Safety, Law, and the Environment (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2004), pp. 78–99.
75 Aaron L. Friedberg, In the Shadow of the Garrison State: America’s Anti-Statism and Its Cold War Grand Strategy (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2000).
76 On that growing conflict, see Cindy Williams, “The Future Affordability of U.S. National Security,” Tobin Paper, October 28, 2011, http://web.mit.edu/ssp/people/williams/Williams_Tobin_paper_102811.pdf; also see Harvey M. Sapolsky, “The Enemy the Pentagon Should Fear Most: Health Care,” National Defense, March 5, 2010, http://www.nationaldefensemagazine.org/archive/2010/March/Pages/EnemyHe….
77 Adam J. Berinsky, “Assuming the Costs of War: Events, Elites, and American Public Support for Military Conflict,” Journal of Politics 69, no. 4 (November 2007): 975–97.
78 John Mueller, “The Iraq Syndrome Revisited: U.S. Intervention, from Kosovo to Libya,” Foreign Affairs, March 28, 2011, http://www.foreignaffairs.com/articles/67681/john-mueller/the-iraq-synd….